Consciousness, Literature and the Arts

Archive

Volume 4 Number 3, December 2003

_______________________________________________________________

Halcour, Dorothée. Wie wirkt Kunst: Zur Psychologie des ästhetischen Erlebens. Frankfurt: Peter Lang 2002, 369 p. ISBN 3-631-39801-8, Price: ?

Reviewed by

Thorsten Botz-Bornstein

Dorothée Halcour’s book What is the Effect of Art? On the Psychology of Aesthetic Experience (written in German) stretches over an impressive 369 pages in small print. The book’s stated aim is to design a “general theory of aesthetic experience” and to subsequently support this theory with the help of a series of case studies. (p. 17) “General” means here that all psychic processes – as well as their coordination – are considered. The author wants to establish three points: What modes of aesthetic experience exist? How do they evolve? And why do they provoke certain reactions?

In principle, the book presents a huge collection of case studies which are described with painstaking exactitude. The energy that went into this book, which was submitted in 2000 as a thesis at the University of Bamberg, Germany, is notable. In his preface to the book, Dietrich Dörner praises the balanced proportion of theoretical organization and empirical description. Having myself made an effort penetrate the forest of facts presented in this book, I must say that I do not share his opinion. A structure more streamlined in terms of theory would have made any appreciation of facts easier and more likely. I am not saying that the introduction of more theoretical material would have made the book more readable. The problem is rather that the book seems to have grown organically out of empirical considerations and that its composition does not seem to have been guided from the beginning by a preexisting, theoretical structure.

A look at the table of contents perhaps makes clear what I mean. The table of contents stretches over six and a half pages. The thirteen chapters are divided into many sub-chapters and sub-sub-chapters etc. All together, there are 192 chapters and sub-chapters. This is more than any normal reader can handle.

The author, in her explanation of the structure of her approach, chooses to work with neutral “components” (Modelbausteine). Her goal is to create an overall image (Gesamtmodell) composed of the different pieces. However, in the end, this “image” remains too kaleidoscopic; an elaboration of a progressive structure would have been more useful than the model of components that can be freely arranged.

In general, the author describes in the most honest way possible what happens when we experience art. One might object that this is very difficult to do unless one already has a theoretical concept in mind by which to restrain the immense field of “aesthetic experience.” Most readers like to discern, after having read the title and the introduction of a book, a hint concerning the direction of the argument along the lines of: ‘she believes that aesthetic experience is like this and not like that and she is going to convince us of her opinion.’ Simply saying: ‘I want to show what aesthetic experience is like,’ is, in my opinion, not enough, at least not with regard to such a subject which is, by nature, extremely vague, open, and furthermore has already been developed into all thinkable directions.

At the beginning one still tries to cling to apparently central questions like: “But what exactly is aesthetic experience? What are the psychological processes which it is accompanied by like? And why is aesthetic experience characterized by such a large variety of possibilities?” (p. 3) While this seems to point to a meta-theme able to coordinate the individual studies, it turns out that very similar sentences occasionally appear in the book until the end, without showing any signs of evolution.

Suggestions as to what a more original theme could be, flow out of the book itself, and are touched upon in many places, but never lead to an end. There is, for example, the interesting “intercultural aspect” of aesthetic experience. The author’s approach consists of presenting a number of paintings to a certain number of people and to note the people’s spontaneous reactions. These people do also come from different cultures (European, Indian).  Instead of using this “intercultural input” as a cornerstone of the research, “the Indians” appear in the middle of the book almost like by coincidence. Interesting points are noted about their “strange” reactions. But soon the “Indians” disappear, only to turn up again here and there towards the end.

            Equally interesting topics are that of the “feeling of competence” and that of the problem of “non-determination,” which are elaborated on more extensively, albeit without reaching a considerable level of originality.

            When it comes to “theories,” they are extremely general, and even further generalized (“How does one create a theory,” sub-chapter 2.2). The already general question “what is aesthetic experience” is further generalized, thus providing new sub-chapters with titles like “why do people deal with art?” (p. 37) This leads to lengthy, more general reflections about “what is art?” and “is the striving after beauty specifically human?” (p. 58), making us loose sight of any possible focal subject. The same is true for basic introductions into the theory of psychological aesthetics, which are not bad as such, but which further postpone the argumentative line that the reader is looking for so desperately.

            Even at an advanced stage of the examination, simplistic phrases about aesthetics are recurrent, such as: “Boredom can arise when all desires are satisfied and no further work remains to be done. There, a free space arises, a space that one normally would like to use in order to recover until the next desire forces us to quit the cozy state of laziness” (p. 64). A preliminary conclusion delivered on p. 67 is no more satisfying as it states that “we can note that indirect and direct factors cooperate within aesthetic experience.” Nor do systematic repetitions of banalities enhance the pleasure of reading: “The reasons why humans deal with paintings can be very different. Aesthetic experience differs, depending on the emotional situation within which the people decide to turn towards the works of art” (p. 68). Or: “People are emotionally different. Therefore it is very likely that they also have different interests. Not all people like to deal with art.” Even if the experiments that follow proved these claims, one wonders if the claims themselves really need to be demonstrated experimentally.

            After having been pushed through hundreds of interviews and their interpretations, through digressions and dispersed, non-progressive arguments, we are denied a conclusion. I must say that I do not really see what I have learned from this book. It might be more interesting for people who work in empirical psychology because it might show them how to empirically proceed in certain situations. The general reader, however, who is versed in philosophy, consciousness studies, or simply in the humanities, is unlikely to gain much from this book. In this sense, the study remains just an exercise.